Takimag has published the following piece I wrote on social conservatism. Unfortunately, they no longer allow comments, which was always half the fun of publishing there.
Is Social Conservatism Necessary?
by James Kalb
January 15, 2009
Is Social Conservatism Necessary?
The voices of conventional wisdom are telling us once again that the Right should reinvent itself, or rather return to its true principles, by abandoning the social issues. Dwight Eisenhower and Barry Goldwater got along without them, so why can’t we do the same today? Instead of worrying about how people live their lives, we should concentrate on trimming government and getting its basic functions right. Let’s create a “conservatism that can win again!”
The argument sounds appealing, in a go-with-the-flow sort of way. It’s nice to think we can make messy issues vanish by ignoring them. The problem, though, is that the argument has no connection to politics as it is now.
Comparisons aren’t always odious, but they’re often unhelpful. The social issues weren’t issues for Eisenhower because they weren’t public issues at all then. Nobody in public life favored abortion or homosexuality, and people thought of Christianity and the more-or-less traditional family as good things we should all support. They were seen as basic to the social background against which political disputes played out. No one was demanding their eradication as a violation of inclusiveness and tolerance.
That was then and this is now. The situation was changing rapidly by the time of the Goldwater candidacy, and by the late sixties the transformation of social relations had become a driving force of politics. “Change” is now the slogan, and that means giving political will a free field of action. The result is that politics now emphasizes abolition of the inherited social background that precedes politics—that imposes limitations, stabilizes human relations, and facilitates informal social functioning, thus making limited government possible.
You don’t get social justice if you don’t deal with social issues. Those who want “change” are the ones most concerned with them. That is why “getting government out of our bedrooms” has turned out to mean sensitivity training, sexual harassment law, compulsory radical redefinition of marriage, and training children to put condoms on cucumbers. To tell a political movement it should avoid comment on such things is to tell it to give up on politics as it actually exists today.
At bottom, the situation is quite simple. Left-liberals believe that society is made up of individuals and legal structures. The only rational and legitimate purpose of the structures is to give the individuals whatever they happen to want, as much and as equally as possible. It follows that the purpose of government, and indeed of morality, is regulating individuals and structures so that career, consumption, and the free choice of hobbies, lifestyles, and indulgences are secured for everyone.
That’s a big ambition—if it weren’t “change” wouldn’t be the ideal—and big ambitions impose big demands. The goal is to give people what they want, and it can only be achieved if what people want fits into the liberal scheme: that is, if it respects the needs of the system and the equal validity of the desires of other individuals.
That means that what people want has to be controlled. Left-liberalism requires us all to become virtuous, where virtue consists in pursuing only legitimate desires—in other words, supporting the system and otherwise minding our own business by concerning ourselves only with tolerant and private goals. Hence PC, and hence the constant re-education initiatives to which we are now subjected.
As long as other people don’t threaten liberalism, we are allowed only positive opinions about them and how they live. The requirement isn’t fad and foolishness, it’s fundamental to present-day politics. The point is abolition of all non-liberal institutions, loyalties, and standards. Those things lead to inequalities not justified on liberal grounds. They propose non-liberal goods—God, country, family, virtue, whatever—that interfere with the smooth operation of a system based on the efficient and equal pursuit of individual desire simply as such.
It is therefore basic to the liberal view that people must be made to view non-liberal goods and institutions as wrong and shameful. In particular, they must be taught to reject with disgust distinctions not related to the functioning of liberal institutions. That’s what “inclusion” and “tolerance” mean.
For example, the system depends on certified expertise, so it’s OK to distinguish between high school grads and college grads, or even between Harvard grads like Obama and State U grads like Palin. There’s nothing wrong with that. In contrast, distinctions related to family, culture, religion, and inherited community must be suppressed. They have at least as much effect as formal education on what we are and do, but they’re bad because they offer an alternative method of social organization and so threaten liberalism. That is why those who make distinctions based on sex, marital status, or community and cultural background must be squashed.
Hence the extraordinary moralism and intolerance of liberalism, its tendency to treat any tolerance for non-liberal standards and distinctions as the worst human quality imaginable. People become intolerant and moralistic when they confront views and conduct that they believe threaten the basis and functioning of social order. And liberals confront such things everywhere. All history, all nature, all culture, and all religion threaten the basis and functioning of a liberal social order. They tell us that human beings cannot be reduced to orderly productive consumers who do what they’re told and only want a life of measured private self-indulgence.
Since human nature is a problem for liberalism, as all indications tell us it is, it has to be denied and stamped out. That is why liberals see hatred, bigotry, and intolerance everywhere. Crypto-Nazis are under every bed. The people can’t be trusted, so they’ve got to be disarmed, supervised, regulated, re-educated, and kept away from anything serious. Popular self-government has to be reined in by courts, bureaucrats, experts, and therapists, and as opportunity offers the government has to dissolve the people and elect a new and more pliant and multicultural one through mass immigration.
If liberals are so moralistic and intolerant, though, why is it rightists who get the rap? That’s mostly a matter of who’s doing the rapping. Mass media, megaversities, and the bureaucratic organization of life generally means that it’s the voices of people who take to large formal structures that get amplified. Those people are left-liberals, because left-liberalism stands for a comprehensive system of top-down social management. It’s an apparatchik’s dream.
From the standpoint of those who identify wholly with that system, right-wingers are indeed bad people. They have their own ideas about what’s required for a tolerable social order, and those ideas usually rely on family, religion, and particular community and culture. That makes rightists squishy-soft at best on racism, sexism, homophobia, and hate. And if they view their left-liberal opponents as the real threat to social order, they’re likely to add moralistic intolerance and the politics of fear to their sins.
Still, the fault is not wholly in the eyes of our opponents. We’re stuck in a slump and need to raise consciousness. Liberalism is based on something very simple, a principle of equality together with a technological approach to human life that reduces rational action to using whatever is available as a means to get what we want. As such, it seems rational, philosophical, and scientific. It’s taught in all the schools because the schools are integrated with mass bureaucratic society, which is happy with a technological approach to things, and it’s easy to train masses of people to understand something so simple and accept it as correct.
Any worthwhile Right must base itself on a more complex, subtle, and adequate understanding that tells us there is more to reality than equality and technology. There are also, it must say, qualities, essences, irreducible particularities, transcendent goods, and what not else. You won’t get far understanding human life if you ignore them. On the other hand, recognizing them makes political life much more problematic than a slogan like “change” suggests. After all, if the social issues are basic, and the most basic social issue is the need for the prepolitical, what do you do about that politically?
So what should the Right do? Not abandon the intuitions that make it Right, especially not for the sake of joining the party that looks stronger at the moment. Instead, we should develop our own views, so that we’re better able to articulate, apply, and press our position. If things aren’t going well the sensible thing is to ask ourselves just what we’re trying to do, and then find new ways to do it.
That process will require courage, grace, high spirits, and intellectual seriousness, together with a freedom of discussion that doesn’t seem to exist anywhere today. That’s good in a way, because it gives us all lots of opportunities for action. Recognition of the situation is the reason for publications like Takimag and organizations like the H.L. Mencken Club and even, on a personal level, for attempts like my own book on liberalism. It’s not likely that any of these efforts will be successful soon, but the point is the trying. On issues that are so basic, giving in for the sake of having an easier time of it is a disgrace.
liberalism emphasizes, not elides, inherited distinctions
They don’t allow comments, but they do give a URL for us to track you down in your lair.
Describing liberalism, you wrote,
That strikes me as a good characterization of liberalism circa 1965. The salient feature of today’s liberalism is the emphasis on some (not all) of these distinctions. Affirmative action is the most obvious example.
Conservatives who buy your characterization of liberalism, or Lawrence Auster’s similar characterization in terms of “the principle of nondiscrimination,” call such liberal discrimination in favor of blacks, women, homosexuals, etc. “hypocritical” or “reverse racism/sexism” or a “double standard.” But calling it that is superficial and misleading. Liberalism is not about erasing inherited distinctions that are an impediment to a rationalist technocracy. Liberal ideologies are not all constructed to further the interests of the New Class, though they’re all constrained by those interests. If liberalism were all about rational class interests, then it would be meritocratic, as it was until a few decades ago.
Liberal distinctions on race, gender, etc. for the purpose of “inclusion” and “diversity” are not accidental. Liberalism does “squash” certain distinctions by certain groups (whites, Christians), as you say, at the same time valorizing distinctions by others. This metadistinction—whose distinctions get valorized, whose get squashed—is essential to contemporary liberalism. In political ideologies there is no such thing as a double standard, only a single standard which someone has misunderstood.
Liberalism is politic
I agree that in political ideologies there is no (or at least only rarely) such a thing as a double standard. Accordingly, I never call liberal treatment of blacks, women, homosexuals, etc. “hypocritical” or “reverse racism/sexism” or a “double standard.” I view those expressions as superficial and misleading.
The effect of liberal identity politics is to disconnect natural and traditional aspects of identity—sex, race, religion, cultural and historical heritage and loyalties—from any social function. Hispanics aren’t encouraged to emphasize Hispanic identity in order to carry on their lives in an independent Hispanic setting based on Hispanic culture, heritage, and loyalties. They are encouraged to emphasize it so they can appeal to lawyers, bureaucrats and judges to keep whites from relying on their own culture, heritage, and loyalties. Emphasis on the identity of non-white non-straight non-Christian non-males means all social institutions have to become multicultural, which means a-cultural, which means money and neutral expert bureaucracy become the sole possible principles of social order.
Liberalism thus makes the New Class the only possible ruling class. It is therefore about suppressing the effect of inherited distinctions that are an impediment to a rationalist technocracy. Since it’s about rational class interests, it can’t be altogether meritocratic. Power is never fanatically principled. Instead, it emphasizes destruction of competing principles of social order over consistent implementation of the meritocratic principles that provide the ostensible justification for its own rule. No surprise there.
Look at Europe
Thanks, that was a very good reply. I disagree with you slightly about meritocracy—I just meant 1965-style meritocracy, not some absolute ideal—but that’s a minor point.
Your points about minorities such as Hispanics in the US are well taken. I agree that liberals use “multiculturalism” as a weapon against traditional (“racist,” “sexist”) culture. Maybe one has to look at Europe, where things are in higher contrast, to see what I meant. For just one example, there was the Archbishop of Canterbury saying nice things about sharia in Britain. Liberals in Europe (I mean “liberal” in the current American sense) really do support minority cultural and political autonomy. They’re OK with moving towards something like the millet system in the Ottoman Empire.
Growing an alien, antiliberal, traditionalist, sharia-ruled minority might be consistent with the perceived interests of the technocrats, but I don’t see that it furthers their real interests. Some people say that they’re creating a mess so that they’ll be the only ones who can manage it, but that seems a little far-fetched. Liberals are not “the only possible ruling class” in this multicultural (as opposed to a-cultural) situation. The Ottomans weren’t liberal.
Anyway, that’s Europe. Since the ideology and rhetoric seem pretty much the same on both sides of the Atlantic, I think the only reason American liberals haven’t gone as far is simply that American minorities, unlike European Muslims, don’t demand autonomy. So that’s my answer: look to Europe.
Strong medicine helps eradicate Euro particularism
I don’t see why allowing some degree of local Sharia rule would be a problem from the liberal view. Establishing Sharia in a Western country is like terrorism. It disrupts established social understandings in a basic way. If you think history is on your side shaking things up makes sense. It accelerates historical change, and liberals think “change” simply as such is a strongly positive term.
Liberalism is progressive and reformist, which means it proceeds step by step. Once the overall legal and social order is disconnected from all particular traditions it will be possible to deal in a rational and uniform way with whatever traditions some people continue to cling to.
From their point of view it’s not “creating a mess so that they’ll be the only ones who can manage it.” It’s more like clearing the ground by eliminating the privileges of any one particularism. Why shouldn’t Sharia have the same status as Anglicanism? The Archbishop is quite right from his point of view as a liberal Christian.
I don’t think it’s likely to lead to a millet system since the state is so much larger now and does so much more, and we have the mass consumer society with pervasive broadband electronic entertainment. Liberals think that welfare state bribes, pop culture dissipations, and careerist and consumerist self-interest will be enough to make minority particularisms nonfunctional. That’s not a crazy point of view.
The Ottoman comparison is an interesting one. The Ottomans like us had a de-particularized meritocratic ruling class, with dynastic rule at the top. We have multiple competing dynasties rather than just one but there’s some similarity in that regard too. It’s true the ultimate justifying theory was Islam rather than liberalism but the latter was institutionally impossible at the time.